Lecture6-new

Lecture6-new - 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering...

Info iconThis preview shows pages 1–6. Sign up to view the full content.

View Full Document Right Arrow Icon

Info iconThis preview has intentionally blurred sections. Sign up to view the full version.

View Full DocumentRight Arrow Icon

Info iconThis preview has intentionally blurred sections. Sign up to view the full version.

View Full DocumentRight Arrow Icon

Info iconThis preview has intentionally blurred sections. Sign up to view the full version.

View Full DocumentRight Arrow Icon
This is the end of the preview. Sign up to access the rest of the document.

Unformatted text preview: 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 6: Continuous and Discontinuous Games Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 23, 2010 1 Game Theory: Lecture 6 Introduction Outline Continuous Games Existence of a Mixed Nash Equilibrium in Continuous Games (Glicksbergs Theorem) Existence of a Mixed Nash Equilibrium with Discontinuous Payoffs Construction of a Mixed Nash Equilibrium with Infinite Strategy Sets Uniqueness of a Pure Nash Equilibrium for Continuous Games Reading: Myerson, Chapter 3. Fudenberg and Tirole, Sections 12.2, 12.3. Rosen J.B., Existence and uniqueness of equilibrium points for concave N-person games, Econometrica , vol. 33, no. 3, 1965. 2 Game Theory: Lecture 6 Continuous Games Continuous Games We consider games in which players may have infinitely many pure strategies. Definition A continuous game is a game hI , ( S i ) , ( u i ) i where I is a finite set, the S i are nonempty compact metric spaces, and the u i : S R are continuous functions. We next state the analogue of Nashs Theorem for continuous games. 3 Game Theory: Lecture 6 Continuous Games Existence of a Mixed Nash Equilibrium Theorem (Glicksberg) Every continuous game has a mixed strategy Nash equilibrium. With continuous strategy spaces, space of mixed strategies infinite dimensional, therefore we need a more powerful fixed point theorem than the version of Kakutani we have used before. Here we adopt an alternative approach to prove Glicksbergs Theorem, which can be summarized as follows: We approximate the original game with a sequence of finite games, which correspond to successively finer discretization of the original game. We use Nashs Theorem to produce an equilibrium for each approximation. We use the weak topology and the continuity assumptions to show that these converge to an equilibrium of the original game. 4 Game Theory: Lecture 6 Continuous Games Closeness of Two Games Let u = ( u 1 , . . . , u I ) and u = ( u 1 , . . . , u I ) be two profiles of utility functions defined on S such that for each i I , the functions u i : S R and u i : S R are bounded (measurable) functions. We define the distance between the utility function profiles u and u as max i I sup s S | u i ( s )- u i ( s ) | . Consider two strategic form games defined by two profiles of utility functions: G = hI , ( S i ) , ( u i ) i , G = hI , ( S i ) , ( u i ) i . If is a mixed strategy Nash equilibrium of G , then need not be a mixed strategy Nash equilibrium of G . Even if u and u are very close, the equilibria of G and G may be far apart. For example, assume there is only one player, S 1 = [ 0, 1 ] , u 1 ( s 1 ) = e s 1 , and u 1 ( s 1 ) =- e s 1 , where e > 0 is a sufficiently small scalar. The unique equilibrium of G is s * 1 = 1, and the unique equilibrium of G is s * 1 = 0, even if the distance between u and u is only 2 e ....
View Full Document

Page1 / 32

Lecture6-new - 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering...

This preview shows document pages 1 - 6. Sign up to view the full document.

View Full Document Right Arrow Icon
Ask a homework question - tutors are online