cient strategy by looking as hard as we can for
cardinals that are not red. The longer we look and
the more creative we can be in trying to find those
non-red cardinals—assuming we don’t find any—
the stronger our original hypothesis becomes.
Popper’s view gives us a more efficient strategy,
and rather than just piling up positive examples,
we strengthen our hypothesis if we attempt vari-
ous ways of showing that the hypothesis is false,
but fail to do so. The method Popper outlines pro-
vides a different way of thinking about the logic
of scientific inquiry and how we might go about
examining our scientific hypotheses.
Testability and Falsifiability
One important aspect of scientific claims that Popper emphasizes is that such claims must
be testable and falsifiable in order to be scientific. A claim is testable if we can come up
with a way of seeing if it is true or not. We can test, for instance, that pure water will freeze
at 0
8
Celsius; we can’t, currently, test the claim that pure water in another galaxy tastes
like root beer. We have no way to develop a method of determining the truth or falsity of
the second claim.
A claim is also said to be falsifiable, in that it could turn out actually to be false, and we
know how that might be shown. For instance, “There are no wild kangaroos in Georgia” is
a falsifiable claim; if we went to Georgia and found some wild kangaroos, we would have
shown it to be false. But what if someone claimed that there are unicorns in North Carolina,
but that they are invisible? Could we ever show such a thing to be false? It would seem to
be the kind of claim that cannot be shown to be false, and so is said to be unfalsifiable.
Most scientists operate with the assumption that any scientific hypothesis must be test-
able and must be the kind of claim that we could show to be false. So if a claim turns out
not to be testable—or if a claim turns out to be one that could never be shown to be false—
the claim isn’t really scientific. For instance, astrologers often make predictions; but if a
Laurence Mouton/Photolibrary
Rather than looking to confirm our
hypothesis, Karl Popper suggests that
we should be looking to disconfirm our
hypothesis.

CHAPTER 5
Section 5.3 Scientific Arguments
claim is something that can’t be shown to be false,
such as “you will meet someone interesting,”
then it isn’t a
scientific
prediction. Or, if a claim
can’t really be tested, it also isn’t scientific. Imag-
ine I give you my lucky rabbit’s foot. How could
we test its success in bringing you luck? Could we
ever show that the rabbit’s foot caused your good
luck, or that not having it caused your bad luck?
Scientists do their best to avoid making claims
that are untestable, as well as claims that can
never be shown to be false. And, oddly enough,
a scientific claim that
always
comes out to be true
will not be a very interesting claim. (Scientists, of
course, argue at some length about whether some
claims are, in fact, falsifiable or testable.)


You've reached the end of your free preview.
Want to read all 36 pages?